Democracy

Someone once said, “In a true democracy, people get the government they deserve.”  I think of this line when people complain about our elected representatives.  We would probably have better government with electoral reform.  Getting rid of Super PACs would be a good start.  However, despite the bias created in politics and the media by the influence of the most wealthy, the fact is that the internet has made it easier than ever in history to gain access to alternative political perspectives, and to determine the facts relevant to any politician’s claims.  (I realize that some people don’t have home internet access, but households without internet connectivity are now a minority, and they will often have access at their local library.  The percentage of households that do have internet access is enough to swing any election in US history.) I subscribe to http://thinkprogress.org, a news blog with a moderately left-of-center perspective.  As a professional philosopher, I also regularly read http://leiterreports.typepad.com.

Here are some other sites that represent “alternatives” to the “mainstream media,” all of which I came up from a quick internet search.  (I’m not endorsing any of them in particular, because I don’t follow them; I’m just letting you know that they are out there.)

  • http://zcommunications.org/zmag (This blog looks like it is a bit to the left of what I regularly read.)
  • http://axisoflogic.com/ (“Axis of Logic staff come from a rich variety of professional backgrounds and life-experiences. All are published authors. All are social and political activists in one form or another. We represent a cross-section of disciplines including homemakers, economists, writers, psychologists, IT professionals, military veterans, former clergy, health care professionals, educators, lawyers and labor leaders. Several of us are entrepreneurs, owning or having owned our own businesses, employing others. … Our purpose is to promote peace, equality, human rights and the right to self determination for all nations throughout the world.”)
  • http://www.corpwatch.org/ (“Non-profit investigative research and journalism to expose corporate malfeasance and to advocate for multinational corporate accountability and transparency. We work to foster global justice, independent media activism and democratic control over corporations. We seek to expose multinational corporations that profit from war, fraud, environmental, human rights and other abuses, and to provide critical information to foster a more informed public and an effective democracy.”)
  • http://www.neweconomics.org/ (New Economics Foundation “was founded in 1986 by the leaders of The Other Economic Summit [TOES] which forced issues such as international debt onto the agenda of the G7 and G8 summits. We are unique in combining rigorous analysis and policy debate with practical solutions on the ground, often run and designed with the help of local people. We also create new ways of measuring progress towards increased well-being and environmental sustainability.”)
  • http://www.wsws.org/ (“The World Socialist Web Site is published by the International Committee of the Fourth International, the leadership of the world socialist movement, the Fourth International founded by Leon Trotsky in 1938.”)
  • And, of course:  http://www.aljazeera.com/

So there are plenty of sources for “alternative” views that are easily available to most Americans.  (In contrast, when I was my kids’ ages, I was curious to read what people with radically different political views thought, but had not access to anything at my local library or bookstore.)  This all leads to a slightly depressing conclusion: most people have views in line with the mainstream of the Democratic and Republican parties (which, as we know, are often not to far away from each other), because that is what they choose to believe, not because the “corporate media” brainwashes them.  Most people want to hear a simple, reassuring story about how the world works that makes minimal demands on them ethically or intellectually.  If they feel they are facing serious problems, they want easy-to-understand solutions that sound like they will work quickly.

Tagged | Leave a comment

Student Reading Habits

I was very interested to discover that a lot of my students have read Tom Wolfe’s The Electric Kool-Aid Acid Test.  I read that when I was in high school, but I would have guessed that no one in their age group had heard of it.  Maybe I should see if they’ve read any Herman Hesse?

Posted in Teaching | 2 Comments

Nisbett’s The Geography of Thought

Several people have recommended to me Richard Nisbitt’s The Geography of Thought:  How Asians and Westerners Think Differently…and Why.   The title is already cringe-inducing. “Asia” is the same as the “Orient,” and as Edward Said demonstrated in his seminal Orientalism, the Orient is a fiction invented by racists and imperialists, particularly in the 19th century.  There really is nothing interesting that people from Afghanistan to Polynesia have in common.  The region spans several major religions, some monotheistic, some polytheistic and some non-theistic.  There is more than one major language family in Asia/the Orient.  There is no common government, or type of government.  There is merely the illusion that “those people” have something in common.  In the book, Nisbett specifies that he has in mind primarily East Asia, but that doesn’t help, because the more than one billion people in those four or five countries (depending upon how you count them) have nothing interesting in common either.

Nisbett’s book is completely vitiated by two major methodological flaws:  (1) he generalizes from small samples to very different populations, and (2) he uses experimental results that test for very different things as evidence for unrelated conclusions.  (1) Nisbitt states explicitly that he wants to generalize over distinctions between the inhabitants of the West (which he states includes “Europeans, Americans, and citizens of the British Commonwealth” [Geography of Thought, p. xvi]) and of Asia (by which he really means East Asia).  However, his experimental populations are in each case very narrow. Sometimes college students in the US vs. college students in the PRC, sometimes “Americans” vs. “Japanese.”  Anyone with passing familiarity with Chinese and Japanese culture knows how very different they are.  (No Chinese or Japanese would think they were the same.)  Europe is also very different from North America, which is reflected in the fact that Nisbitt’s generalizations don’t even hold for Europe (by his own admission [Geography of Thought, p. 84]).  In short, you can’t infer from a difference between college students in Ann Arbor and Beijing what the average person in Seoul or Tokyo thinks.  (2) One conclusion that Nisbit tries to establish is that “Westerners” see a world composed of independent “objects,” whereas “Asians” see a world composed of continuous “substances.”  What is his evidence for this?  Show subjects a pyramid made of cork, tell them, “This is a ‘dax,’” and then ask them to pick out a “dax” from a collection of other things.  The American usually pick a pyramid, while the Japanese usually pick something else made of cork (Geography of Thought, p. 81).   Intriguing, but this does not reveal any difference in assumptions about individualism and holism.  Both the Americans and the Japanese are abstracting from the particular “object” (this cork pyramid) and identifying a general category that it belongs to (being pyramid shaped or being made of cork).  Aristotle would describe these as the material cause and the formal cause of the item in question. In neither case does the process of going from the particular to the category show that one group is less committed to “objects.”

Likewise, it is intriguing that Japanese are more likely to notice background differences between two pictures while Americans are more likely to notice foreground differences (Geography of Thought, p. 95).  But how on earth does this show that the Japanese are more holistic?  Noticing individual objects in the background of a picture is different from noticing individual objects in the foreground, but in each case a person is identifying individual objects.

I could go on indefinitely.  Nisbett’s work consists of page after page of wild generalizations, imprecise characterizations, and non sequiturs.

Posted in Philosophy | Leave a comment

Methodological Solipsism

Descartes makes methodological solipsism almost compulsive for later philosophers. (How is that for opening with a grand pronouncement?)

By “methodological solipsism” I mean an approach to philosophy that claims we have privileged access to our own mental states, we have such access to nothing else, and one of philosophy’s primary tasks is to show how to get from subjective states to whatever else we wish to accept or justify.  Descartes thought he could make the jump from subjective “ideas” to external “substances” by proving that there is an all-good and all-powerful God, who would not allow us to be deceived by our “clear and distinct ideas.”  Philosophers in the empiricist tradition, like Hume, tried to show how our knowledge of the world could be constructed out of our “impressions.” Most philosophers thinks both failed in their respective projects.

Methodological solipsism is a seductive line of thought, and is hard to escape once it ensnares you.  But why should we accept it?  There are at least two ways to argue for it.

(1) Descriptively:  we do, in fact, “start” from subjective experiences.  This seems obviously false, though.  Is the claim that, when I wake up in the morning, I have experiences that are properly categorized as purely subjective, and that I go through a process of gradually inferring the existence of other things?  I don’t do that, and I doubt if others do.  I wake up to what I experience as a world of independent objects, of which I am a part:  alarm clock, bed, wife, my body, etc.  Experiences that we regard as subjective are very special cases.  Perhaps I hear a “ringing” in my ears, and I wonder whether it is a real sound, or just a symptom of an ear infection.  I ask other people whether they hear it, and if they do not I take an aspirin and the ringing goes away.  But certainly looking at my dog and hearing him bark is not like that.

(2) Prescriptively:  although we normally experience what we take to be a world of independent entities of which we are a part, all we are entitled to accept as starting points of warranted reasoning are our subjective experiences. But what is inferentially special about our subjective experiences?  Descartes said that we cannot be deceived about the fact that we are thinking.  But I certainly can be deceived about the content of my ideas.  Descartes likes to talk about dreams.  The content of dreams is notoriously inchoate, though.  Did I dream that I held a cat?  Or was it a skunk?

“So much the worse!” crows the skeptic.  “You see that you cannot even be certain of the content of your subjective experiences.”  True, but this just raises again the issue of why the methodological solipsist insists that we privilege them.  Our subjective experiences are one particular kind of our experiences, and they are often very difficult to single out and identify.  I’m looking at a computer screen now.  It requires a lot of mental discipline to focus on my subjective experience of the screen, rather than the screen itself. Why not take for granted my belief that I am looking at a computer screen, unless a specific concern leads me to doubt this particular belief.

So why not conduct philosophy the way we conduct ordinary conversations?  We are fellow humans who share a common world.  We sometimes discover that what we see in the world is different.  And that leads us to talk about why we see the world that way.  Philosophy is that conversation about what and why we see in the world.

Of course, you can disagree with me, but if you’re a methodological solipsist you’re just disagreeing with a disagreeable subjective experience.  Just take an aspirin and maybe I’ll go away.

Posted in Philosophy | Leave a comment

The Value of Philosophy

A student pointed out to me Gary Gutting’s recent article for the NY Times philosophy column, “The Stone.”  Previous installments of “The Stone” have come under fire for what some professional philosophers regard as inaccurate claims and sloppy reasoning.  Gutting’s article addressed the question of what the point or purpose of philosophy is.  I think some of his observations are very helpful.  For example, philosophy helps us to “clarify what our basic beliefs mean or entail.”

Let me illustrate Gutting’s point with an example of my own.  In my intro to philosophy class, we discuss what makes an act of violence (like the 9/11 attacks) terrorism.  They usually zero in on the fact that terrorism is violence that targets innocent civilians.  Then I ask them to consider the US bombings on Hiroshima and Nagasaki.  Those cities were chosen as targets in large part because they were untouched by previous bombing.  (Dropping an A-bomb on Tokyo wouldn’t show too much, because Tokyo, the center of the Japanese military and government, had already been destroyed by US bombing.)  Why had Hiroshima and Nagasaki been spared previous bombing?  Not out of humanitarian reasons.  They simply weren’t particularly valuable as military targets.  However, there were lots of civilians waiting to be killed (pardon the gruesome expression) in both cities, so they were “good” targets for the A-bombs.  The obvious question students have to wrestle with is whether the Hiroshima and Nagasaki bombings were acts of terrorism because they targeted civilians.  If not, why not? And what implications does this have for whatever will be the next use of the US military force?  Hardly moot questions, I think.

But philosophers like to disagree, so I have some nits to pick with Gutting’s piece.  He castigates Descartes for trying to “provide a foundation for beliefs that need no foundation,” and praises Hume for “rejecting…the foundationalist conception of philosophy.”  Descartes is a foundationalist, but I think it is worth stressing that he does not ask us to entertain the possibility that a deceitful demon is tricking him into believing in an illusory world because he likes abstract philosophical puzzles.  Descartes lived in the aftermath of the schism between Catholicism and Protestantism, the furious debates between Ptolemaic and Copernican astronomers, as well as revolutionary changes in politics, the arts, etc.  He, like so many thinking people in his era, was unsure what the truth was.  It won’t do to say, “Tut, tut, Rene!  You hardly need a justification for the belief that you have a soul separate from your body.  Why bother to argue for it!  As if any of us doubted that.”  Well, people questioned the existence of the soul back then as they do now.  Descartes tried the method of radical doubt in order to see what, if anything, survived the process of doubt, hoping that he could find a firm foundation for knowledge.  Did he succeed?  Almost no one thinks so, but you won’t understand what he is doing unless you see why he is doing it.  In addition (although this is too much to go into here), many students and even professional philosophers who deny Descartes “thrice before the cock crows” accept many of Descartes’ basic presuppositions, whether they know it or not.

I’m also not happy with Gutting’s characterization of Hume as an anti-foundationalist.  Hume does have a famous response to skepticism in the Treatise, where he recommends  doing some everyday things (go for a walk, play some backgammon) until your skeptical concerns start to seem unreal and irrelevant.  However, Hume is ultimately as much of a foundationalist as Descartes.  Hume’s foundation, that which he thinks cannot be doubted, is immediate sensory experience.  The “impressions” of our senses are the basis of our “ideas” (the latter being merely faint copies of them), and all our mental content is derived from them.  Hume’s empiricism doesn’t succeed either.  But, once again, we need to see that he is a foundationalist, and recognize how latent empiricism lurks in the “common sense” of most college-educated people even today.

Of course, it is hard to write a brief editorial about philosophy and be precise.  Perhaps Gutting would have made all these qualifications and more if he had more space, or were directly addressing other philosophers.  (I sometimes simplify positions myself when trying to explain them to beginning students.)  And perhaps I really have misread Descartes and/or Hume myself.  But, as I sometimes tell my students, how will you know whether what you are saying makes sense or is defensible unless you discuss it with someone else?

Posted in Philosophy | Leave a comment

Student Question on Meta-Philosophy

Every time I teach intro to philosophy (we call it Problems of Philosophy, a title I’m not especially fond of, but that’s best saved for another post), I have at least one student who is some combination of a radical subjectivist and an extreme skeptic.  This can really block the student’s learning, because students like this sometimes can’t quite see the point of discussing and evaluating different viewpoints, or offering arguments in favor of or against them.

This semester, one of my students followed up on several long conversations after class and in my office hours by sending me an email in which she expressed some of her subjectivist objections to philosophy as a discipline.  One of her concerns was that the methodology of philosophy seems to her to require accepting certain premises without further argumentation.  She concluded by thanking me for allowing her to “challenge” my “great patience” with her many questions.  Here is part of my reply:

“Great patience” is meant to be challenged. 🙂

I think it is impractical to not make judgments of truth and falsity, and to try to avoid giving justifications for one’s beliefs.  However, I could be wrong.  (Or could I?)

Perhaps a general way to address your concerns is this.  Part of what philosophers disagree about is the methodology of philosophy.  Indeed, I teach an advanced seminar on just this topic.  As we read through the philosophers in this course, you will see different views about how philosophy works.  Descartes sees philosophy as beginning with indubitable premises that all humans must share.  Hume sees philosophy as closely related to natural science.  The hermeneutic philosophers, of which Richard Bernstein is our representative, think philosophy is a form of dialogue aimed at achieving agreement that is not coerced. 

These are just three possibilities. 

Posted in Philosophy, Teaching | Leave a comment

Analytic Philosophy

I am blessed with outstanding junior colleagues working in a variety of sub-fields of philosophy.  One of them gave a presentation the other day on how to handle vague terms.  The talk was impressively precise, and I think I will fail to do justice to it here.  But allow me to try and give the gist.

“Salty” is a vague term.  If I start with water with no salt in it, it clearly is not salty.  If the water has 10% salt, it is definitely salty.  But what if it is somewhere in the middle?  Suppose I am unsure whether to apply the term “salty” to a given sample of water.  Since I am conflicted, I might say that I should be 50% confident that the water is salty and 50% confident that it is not.  However, this turns out to give results that are implausible for technical reasons.  Instead, my colleague proposes a particular function that maps interpretations of “salty” onto a confidence range.  I might end up with something like, “I have no lower than  35% confidence that the water is salty, but no more than 65% confidence that it is salty.”

Again, I’m not sure I’ve done justice to the talk (which was, to some extent, over my head because of the technicalities involved).  However, I do have a couple of observations.  (1) The talk illustrates a style of “analytic philosophy” that uses examples that are far removed, sometimes intentionally, from ordinary experience.  As I noted in the discussion period after the talk, no chef or foodie would simply say “This is salty” and not have a more specific meaning in mind.  They might mean, “This is TOO salty for the kind of dish it is,” or “The salt overwhelms the taste of the potatoes.”  As a result of (1), I think (2) the particular analysis given does not provide useful information.  If someone tells me that “The likelihood that you will complete your inside straight on the river is only 8%,” they have given my useful information that I know how to act on.  However, a chef or gourmet who is told (or determines herself) that “my confidence that this is salty is in between 35% and 65%” does not have a premise of practical reasoning.

I should note that all my junior colleagues seem much smarter and more energetic than I am.  Consequently, if you are unsure whom to believe, they are probably a better bet.  Nonetheless, when sending my steak back, I refuse to say simply, “It’s salty.”

Posted in Philosophy | Leave a comment

Vices

Aristotle said that virtues are means between extremes.  He is not saying that everyone should strive to be mediocre and emotionally tepid in everything that they do.  The mean is relative to each situation.  So sometimes you are following the mean by being distraught (like when a loved one passes away), while other times you are following the mean by being joyful (like when your child is born).  The person of virtue consistently responds with the “mean” reaction in a particular sphere of experience.  In the sphere of experience relating to dangers, courage is the mean between “rashness” (a tendency to not fear what is fearful, or to rush in to face foolish dangers) and “cowardice” (a tendency to fear too much, or to give in to fear too easily).

This account is not unproblematic.  And it certainly needs to be supplemented to be fully adequate.  (Aristotle and later Aristotelians have done some of that supplementing, but not all that is needed.)  But it is often a good starting point when thinking about virtues and vices.

Consider two extremes: naivete and cynicism.  I’m not sure we have a generally accepted name for the mean state between these extremes.  “Realism” is tempting, but that’s already a technical term in philosophy.  Perhaps “reflectiveness”?  Although they are opposite extremes, naivete and cynicism are very similar.  Both the naive and the cynical assume that their prejudgments are accurate; each is disposed to a particular kind of prejudgment of the motives of others; neither is sufficiently responsive to evidence that their prejudgments are wrong.  The naive person assumes that person A is motivated by kindness and integrity. He will cling to this assumption in the face of behavior from A that makes this incredibly implausible.  The cynical person assumes that person B is motivated by selfishness.   He will attribute to B the most unusual beliefs, for which there is no evidence, and invent complicated variations of self-interest, in order to maintain his presumptions.

Ironically, both the cynical and the naive person tend to assume that humans are rational.  They are blind to the all-too-common cases of the basically kind person taking exactly the wrong means to help others, or the self-interested person acting self-destructively.

Posted in Philosophy | Leave a comment

Poker

I was interviewed today (for an article about unusual hobbies of Vassar professors) about playing in last summer’s World Series of Poker in Las Vegas.  I don’t think everything I said will make the article, but part of what I said is that poker is a game of skill with a luck component.  Because of the luck component, bad and mediocre players will sometimes win in the short run.  But because of the skill component, good players will win in the long run.

The skill element of poker falls into three areas.  First, there are purely mathematical factors.  For example, if you are drawing to an inside straight, you need to get better than 11:1 on your money for your call to be profitable.  Second, there are game theoretical considerations.  However a person plays his cards, he is following a strategy of some kind (whether he is conscious of what that strategy is or not).  For every strategy, there is a counter-strategy that exploits it.  You have to figure out what strategy your opponent is following, and adopt the appropriate counter-strategy.  Conversely, if your opponent adopts a good counter-strategy, you must change your strategy to one that exploits their counter-strategy.  Third, there are psychological aspects to the game.  This includes things like reading your opponent’s “tells.”  However, an even more important part of poker psychology is maintaining your own focus and discipline.  Because of the luck factor in poker, you will sometimes play a hand perfectly, and lose anyway.  This is very frustrating, and some players cannot handle those situations.  They go on “tilt” (or, as it is sometimes more colorfully described, “full on monkey tilt”), and start making bad mathematical and strategic decisions.  You have to be able to play your “A game” at all times.

Posted in Poker | Comments Off on Poker

Evaluating Teaching

It’s the beginning of a new semester.  One of the things that this means is that I have gotten the numerical and written feedback from students for the courses I taught last semester.  The numerical feedback is what counts for promotion and merit pay increases, but, ironically, I take more seriously the written feedback, even though only I get to see it.  (By College regulations, faculty may not include the written feedback in their “packets” for promotion and tenure.)

After the first semester I taught at Vassar, I saw my numerical evaluations and was very pleased with myself … until I noticed the note attached from my Chair, who said, “I’m sure you find these numbers very disappointing, but don’t despair.  Many professors improve a great deal after their first couple of semesters.”  It turns out that evaluations considered very solid at other schools I’ve taught at, or even in other departments at Vassar, are not considered good enough by the Philosophy Department.

Through hard work and listening to my students, I’ve gotten much better at teaching.  On the numerical scores, 4s and 5s are considered good, and we hope to have 75% or more of the responses be in this range, particularly on three “key questions”:  “How well the course met its objectives as stated by instructor,” “Overall effectiveness of instructor,” and “As a result of this course, how much have your knowledge and understanding of the subject matter increased?”  In my Early Chinese Philosophy class, I got 100% 4s and 5s on the first two questions (92% and 82% 5s, respectively) and 93% 4s and 5s on the third question (62% 5s).  This is pleasant, but as I say I don’t weight it too heavily.  There is actually no empirical evidence that scoring well on our numerical student satisfaction surveys shows you are doing a good job of teaching knowledge and skills to your students.

However, the written evaluations give me more content. I always get compliments for being open-minded:  “I really appreciated that you were enormously open-minded while acknowledging your own bias/position.”  I am surprised by how often students use the word “inspiring”:  “has inspired me to take other philosophy courses”; “inspired me to continue in my studies in the philosophy department”;  “you are an academic and lifelong inspiration.”  I worry that this reflects how “uninspiring” so much of our culture is, though.  After being exposed to nothing but video games and Jersey Shore, it’s hard to not be inspired by a professor (any professor) teaching Confucius and Aquinas.

I think my favorite comments this time around, though, were the ones written in blotchy ink, saying, “Really enjoyed the class.  Regret waiting till senior year to take a class with you.  My pen is running out of ink.”

Posted in Teaching | Comments Off on Evaluating Teaching